CHAPTER 9
HegelÕs Phenomenology of Spirit: post- Kantianism in a new
vein
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich
Hegel was born in 1770 in Stuttgart and died in 1831 in Berlin. Entering the
Protestant Seminary in Tubingen in 1788, he had befriended and roomed with Friedrich
Holderlin, and later they shared a room and
friendship with Friedrich Schelling (who was younger than them). After
graduating from the Seminary, he took a long and awkward path to philosophy; he
became a "house-tutor" for two different families and experienced a
failed independent career as an author before becoming an unpaid lecturer in
philosophy at Jena and a co-editor with Schelling
of the Schellingian Critical Journal of Philosophy, which,
when it ceased publication, turned Hegel simply into an unpaid lecturer
at Jena. After that position also collapsed, he became first a newspaper editor
and then a high-school teacher in Nuremberg (where he married a member of the
Nuremberg patriciate), and finally in 1816, at the
age of 46, he acquired his first salaried academic position in Heidelberg. In
1818 he accepted a position as professor at the Berlin university, where he
quickly rose to fame as the European phenomenon known simply as
"Hegel." pp. 217-218
In
one of his letters to Schelling, written shortly after his graduation from
the Seminary in 1793, he remarked that "from the Kantian philosophy
and its highest completion I expect a
revolution in Germany. p. 218
Hegel
served as a house-tutor in Frankfurt between 1797 and 1801, a position his old
friend, Holderlin, had found for him, and while there
he came under the influence of Holderlin's own
revolutionary attempts at developing post-Kantian thought. For Hegel, Holderlin had shown how Fichte's
development of post-Kantian thought failed to understand the way in which there
had to be a deeper unity between subject
and object, how the distinction between the subjective
and the objective could not itself be a subjective or an objective distinction,
and that our awareness of the distinction itself presupposes some background
awareness of their deeper unity. Underlying the rupture between our
experience of the world and the world itself, however, was a deeper sense of a notion of truth - of
"being," as Holderlin called it - that
was always presupposed in all our otherwise fallible encounters with each other
and the world. Hegel took those
views with him when he left Frankfurt for Jena in 1801. p. 218
SUBJECTIVE AND OBJECTIVE POINTS OF VIEW:
Although technically Hegel first published a book in 1797 - an anonymously
published translation of and commentary on a French language radical critique
of the German-speaking Bernese patriciate (done while
serving as a house-tutor for one of the leading families of the same patriciate) - his first philosophical book (and
certainly the first that carried his name on it as the author) was his 1801 essay, The Difference between
Fichte's and Schelling's Systems of Philosophy. In it, he offered an argument
that Schelling's philosophy (which until that point had been generally taken by
the German philosophical public as only a variant of Fichte's thought) actually
constituted an advance on Fichte's
philosophy. Schelling had argued
that Fichte's key claim - that the difference between the subjective and the
objective points of view had to be itself a subjective distinction,
something that the "I" posits - was itself flawed, since the line
between the "I" and the "Not-I" was not itself absolute;
one can draw it one way or another, idealistically
or dogmatically, depending on what
one's character inclined one to do. Instead, there had to be an overarching point of view that was presupposed
by both points of view, which Schelling called the "absolute" and
which, as encompassing both the subjective and objective points of view,
was itself only apprehendable by an
"intellectual intuition." In his Difference book,
Hegel endorsed that line of thought, giving it some added heft by
arguing that, in doing so, Schelling had
implicitly brought to light what was really the upshot of
Kant's three Critiques, namely, that the sharp
distinction that Kant seemed to be making between
concept and intuition was itself only an abstraction from a more basic, unitary
experience of ourselves as already being in the world. pp. 218-219
HEGELÕS
REJECTION OF KANTÕS DISTINCTION BETWEEN CONCEPTS
AND INTUITIONS: On Hegel's recounting
in the Difference book, Fichte,
having in effect dropped Kant's requirement of intuition altogether, was
then forced into understanding the "Not-I" as only a
"posit" that the "I" had to construct for itself, and by virtue of that move
was driven to the one-sided conclusion that the difference between the subjective and the objective had to be itself a
subjectively established difference. Hegel hinted that Schelling's
conception of the "absolute" already indicated that Fichte's views concerning both the sharp
differentiation between concept and intuition and the subsequent downplaying of the role of intuitions
were themselves unnecessary, and, on the first page of the essay, Hegel noted
that "[i]n the principle of the deduction of the categories Kant's
philosophy is authentic idealism"
- that is, that the part of the Critique where Kant wishes to show that there can be no
awareness of unsynthesized intuitions was
implicitly the part where Kant himself showed that the distinction between
concepts and intuitions is itself relative to an over all background understanding of what normative
role various elements of our cognitive practices must and do play.3
Classifying something as a
"concept" or an "intuition," that is, is already putting it
into the place it plays in the practice of giving and asking for reasons, in
what Hegel (following Schelling's usage) took to calling the "Idea,"
which Hegel eventually more or less identified as the "space of reasons"
(although this was not his term).4
pp. 219-220
DUALITIES: That such oppositions (such as those between nature and freedom, subject and object, concepts and intuitions)
have come on the agenda of philosophers in 1800 only indicates, he argued, that
something deeper was at stake. p.
220
MODERNITY AND RELIGION: FREEDOM AND
ABSOLUTION: The guiding question behind almost all of them was one that had
been nagging at him since he was a student at the Protestant Seminary in Tubingen:
what would a modern
religion look like,
and was it possible to have a modern religion that would satisfy our needs in the way that classical religions seemed
to have satisfied the needs of the ancients? The need that modern religions were called upon to satisfy was, of
course, the need to be free in a Kantian or post-Kantian sense, and the
question that Hegel was implicitly asking was: what would it take to be
able to lead one's own life, to have a life of one's
own, to be, in the language that
Kant had introduced, autonomous, self-legislating? pp. 220-221
As he was finally running out of money and
all hope for any future employment as an academic, he set to work on his
greatest piece, the epochal Phenomenology
of Spirit, finished in 1806 and published around Easter, 1807. p. 221
One of Hegel's students in Berlin, Karl
Michelet, claimed that Hegel took to describing his 1807 Phenomenology if Spirit as his own
"voyage of discovery.Ó p.
221
He never lectured on the Jena Phenomenology while
in Berlin, although he did lecture on some sections of it that he had reworked
into his Encyclopedia of the
Philosophical Sciences, and
near the end of his life he even disavowed it as the proper "introduction" to his system of philosophy
at all, claiming that his
later Encyclopedia now formed the proper introduction. (The Encyclopedia was first published in 1817 and went through
published revisions and
expansions in 1827 and 1830.) However, he continued to give copies of the Phenomenology to friends and notable visitors, and in 1831 he signed a contract to publish a revised
edition of it. (He died before he could do much work on it, and although the
revisions were clearly intended only to be minor, we will, of course, never
know what Hegel might have done once he began work on it.) p. 222
Not surprisingly, interpreters have always
had trouble making sense of the book; it has been held, variously, to be a
"coming of age" novel (a Bildungsroman), a new version of the divine comedy, a tragedy, a tragi-comedy,
a work in epistemology, a philosophy of history, a treatise in Christian
theology, and an announcement of the death of God. p. 222
Hegel intended the book to satisfy the needs of contemporary (European)
humanity: it was to provide an education,
a Bildung, a formation for
its readership so that they could come to grasp with who
they had become (namely, a people individually and
collectively "called" to be free), why they
had become those people, and why that had been necessary. In that respect,
the Phenomenology was a completely post-Kantian work: it
intended to show its readership
why "leading one's own life," self-determination, had become
necessary for "us moderns" and what such "self-legislation"
actually meant. p. 222
TRUTH-MAKERS AND THEIR PROGRESSIVE IDENTIFICATION: Hegel called this a thesis about Òconsciousness.Ó If we begin with our consciousness of singular objects present to our senses ("sense-certainty," an awareness of "things" that is supposedly prior to fully fledged judgments), and hold that what makes those awarenesses true are in fact the singular objects themselves, then we take those objects to be the "truth-makers" of our judgments about them; however, in taking these objects to be the "truth-makers" of our awareness of them, we find that our grasp on them dissolves (or, alternatively: that in their role as "truth-makers" they themselves dissolve). The impetus for such dissolution lies in the way our taking them to play the role of "truth-makers" in that way turns out to involve ineliminable tensions or contradictions in our very "takings" themselves, and the result, so Hegel argued, is that, in the process of working out those tensions, we discover that it could not be the singular objects of sense-certainty that had been playing the normative role of "making" those judgments of sense-certainty true, but the objects of more developed, more mediated perceptual experience had to have been playing that role. (The objects of "sense-certainty" turned out, that is, not to be playing the normative role that the proponents of "sense-certainty" had originally taken them to be playing; something else, namely, perceptual objects as complexes of individual things instantiating general properties, turned out to be playing that role.) Or, to put it more dialectically, the tensions and contradictions involved in taking singular objects to be making our judgments about them true require us to acknowledge that something else must be playing that role (and that, implicitly, we are already relying on that "something else" in making such judgments in the first place).
p. 223
HOLISM THESIS:
The dialectic inherent in Jacobi's "sense-certainty" thus turns on
our being required to see the "truth-maker" of even simple judgments
about the existence of singular things of experience as consisting of more complex
unities of individual-things-possessing-general-properties of which we are
"perceptually," and not
simply "directly" aware.
That is, we can legitimate judgments about singular objects only by referring them to our awareness of
them as singular objects possessing general properties, which, in turn, requires us to legitimate them in terms of
our take on the world in which they appear as such
perceptual objects. p. 223
ACCOUNTING FOR OBJECTIVITY DEMANDS THE ÒNORMATIVE
TURNÓ: What that requires us to see, so Hegel argues, is that the conception
that there is any object or set of
objects (even conceived as the world itself) that on its own, independently of our own activities, makes our
judgments about those things true - as it were, something on which we could
rely to keep us on the right track independently of any of our own ways
of taking it, of our "keeping ourselves" on the right track - is
itself so deeply ridden with tensions and contradictions in its own terms that
it is untenable. The whole outlook of
seeking the "objects" of some kind of direct awareness that would
make that awareness true independently of our "taking" it to be
such-and-such is so riddled with tensions that it requires us to acknowledge
that part of that awareness has to do with the ways we "take" those
objects. We must acknowledge, as Kant put it, that it must be possible for an "I think" to accompany all our
consciousness of things. The
dialectic of "consciousness"
therefore requires us to focus on how we hold ourselves to norms, and how we cannot rely on something
independently of our own activities to keep us on the straight and narrow path
to truth. p. 224
INTUITION = THE GIVEN = THE MYTH OF THE
GIVEN: BEYOND THE CONCEPT/INTUITION DUALISM: The opening chapters of the Phenomenology
provided Hegel with a way of stating some Kantian points without, so
he thought, having to commit himself to (what he regarded as) either the unfortunate and untenable Kantian dualism
between concepts and intuitions or to the Kantian mechanism of the "imposition" of concepts on
sensibility to which Kant had been driven by virtue of accepting
that dualism (that is, to seeing intuition as providing neutral
content on which an organizational, conceptual scheme was then imposed). pp. 224-225
In showing that the normative demands
made by "consciousness" (that is, the norms governing judgments about
objects of which we are aware), we are
driven to comprehend that our mode of taking them to be such-and-such plays
just as important a role in the cognitive enterprise as do the objects
themselves or our so-called direct awareness of them. That itself therefore
raises the question: what are the
conditions under which our "takings" of them might be successful? In
particular, how might we distinguish what only seems to be "the way we
must take them" from the "way they really are?" p.
225
KANTIAN SPONTANEITY
AND THE QUESTION OF HOW SUCH A RULE GAINS A ÒGRIP ON USÓ: In the next section of the Phenomenology, titled "Self-Consciousness," Hegel carried out his most radical
reformulation of Kantian philosophy, drawing deeply on Fichte's, Holderlin's,
and Schelling's influences, while giving them a thoroughly new twist. Kant
had said that, in making judgments,
we follow the "rule" spontaneously prescribed for us by the concepts
produced by our own intellects (the "understanding"), and had
argued that the necessary, pure "rules" or "concepts of the
understanding" were generated
by the requirements of ascribing experiences to (in Kant's own terms) a
"universal self-consciousness" - that is, what were the
requirements for any agent's "I think" to be able to accompany
all his representations. Hegel's way of
putting that Kantian question had to do with what in general could ever possess
the authority to determine what counted as the rules of such a shared,
"universal self-consciousness." The outcome of the dialectic of
"consciousness" had shown that it depended on how we were taking things, and that, in turn,
raised the issue of what we might be seeking to accomplish in taking things one
way as opposed to another. Thus, the
issue turned on what purposes might be normatively in play (or what basic needs
might have to be satisfied) in taking things one way as opposed to
another. p. 225
INCORPORATION THESIS & PRACTICAL
RATIONALITY AS SELF-SATISFACTION: However, practical desires are themselves like
sensations in cognition; they acquire a normative significance only to the
extent that we confer such a significance on them (or, in Kant's language, only as we
incorporate them into our maxims). That
means that agents are never simply satisfying desires; they are satisfying a project that they have (at least implicitly) set
for themselves in terms of which desires have a
significance that may not correspond to their intensity. The agent, that is, has a "negative" relation to those desires, and thus the agent never simply
"is" what he naturally is but "is what he is" only in terms
of this potentially negative self-relation to himself - his (perhaps
implicit) project for his life, not "life" itself, determining the
norms by which he ranks his desires.8
pp. 225-226
It cannot
be simply "reason" itself, since that would beg the question of what
purposes the use of reason best serves (or whether those purposes are to take
precedence over any others in any non-question-begging way, or what even
counts as a reason to whom).
p. 226
KANTIAN
PARADOX SOLVED: In putting the question in that way, Hegel raised the issue
that Kant had himself brought out so prominently in his own practical
philosophy, which we have called the "Kantian
paradox." Kant had argued that we must practically take ourselves to
be self-determining, that what we as agents were "ultimately about"
was freedom in this radical sense (or, to put it in slightly non-Kantian terms, there would be no point to our lives if
they did not somehow embody this kind of freedom). But if the will imposes
such a "law" on itself, then it must do so for a reason (or else be
lawless); a lawless will, however, cannot be regarded as a free will; hence,
the will must impose this law on itself for a reason that then cannot itself be
self-imposed (since it is required to impose any other reasons). The "paradox" is that we seem to
be both required not to have an antecedent reason for the legislation of any
basic maxim and to have such a reason. Kant's own way out was simply to invoke
the "fact of reason," which from the standpoint of the post-Kantians
amounted more to stating the "paradox" than actually dealing with it. p. 226
Like many others,
Hegel, too, was unsatisfied with that result. However, unlike Schelling,
Hegel did not think that any kind of metaphysics of Naturphilosophie would
satisfactorily resolve the issue, since such a Naturphilosophie either
ultimately rested on some form of "intellectual
intuition" (which, as Hegel was later to remark in his lectures on the
history of philosophy, basically would have the same value as consulting an oracle); or, in light of Kant's destruction of pre-critical metaphysics,
it simply begged all the questions it was trying to answer. Instead, something basic about our conception of
the nature of agency itself had to be invoked. It is probably not going too far to say that Hegel viewed the
"Kantian paradox" as the basic problem that all post-Kantian
philosophies had to solve; and the solution had to
be to face up to the paradox and to see how we might make it less lethal to our conception of agency
while still holding onto it, all in terms of integrating it into some overall conception of agency that showed how
the paradox was in fact livable and conceivable. pp. 226-227
SPALTUNG: What the "Kantian
paradox" seemed to call for was for an agent to split himself in two - in
effect, for "me" to issue a law to myself that "I" could
then use as a reason to apply the law to myself (what Hegel in his post-Phenomenology writings
liked to call becoming the "other of itself," "das
Andere seiner selbst,"
a phrase he claimed to
take from Plato). 9
Splitting the agent in two - seeing each as the "negative" of
the other, in Hegel's terms - does nothing to solve the problem, since such a
view cannot adjudicate which of the two sides of the same agent is to have
priority over the other; it cannot, that
is, show how splitting myself in two somehow "binds" one of my parts
because of legislation enacted by the other, nor can it even show how it would
be possible for me correctly to grasp the rule to which I am supposedly
subjecting myself. p. 227
MUTUAL
RECOGNITION AS THE LOGIC OF COMMITMENTS AND ENTITLEMENTS: Hegel's resolution of the Kantian paradox was to see it in social terms.
Since the agent cannot secure any bindingness for the principle simply on
his own, he requires the recognition of another agent of it as binding on both of them. Each demands recognition from
the other that the "law" he enacts is authoritative (that is, right).
In Hegel's terms, the
other agent must become the "negative" of the first agent, and
vice versa; Hegel in fact speaks of this rather colorfully as a "doubling" (Verdopplung) of self-consciousness. II Or, to put
it another way, the first agent demands that the other agent recognize his
entitlement to the commitment he has undertaken and vice versa. This set of
demands leads to a struggle for recognition, since at the beginning of the struggle, each agent is in effect lawless, simply imposing a set
of demands for reasons that, from the standpoint of the other agent, must seem
to be without warrant. Each agent just chooses his own maxims (perhaps as those that satisfy his desires,
perhaps not) and demands of the other agent that he confer an entitlement on
him. pp. 227-228
One becomes, that is, the author of the law, the other becomes the agent subject to the law. p. 228
The master remains caught in the
"Kantian paradox" without any real way out; for his edicts to have the kind of
normative authority he claims (even desperately desires) them to have, he must be able to make his will "stick," to be able to enforce his will on the vassal;
he attempts to "prove" that his will is binding by having the vassal
slavishly work for him, but that only makes him more dependent on the vassal. p. 228
The vassal, on the other hand, by internalizing the master's sense of law as
what is right, as the objective point of view itself, also thereby through his work for the master ceases to
remain a lawless agent. Through his work, the vassal learns what it
means to subject oneself to the law, and, as having been shaken to his foundations in the struggle
for recognition (by the fear of death), the vassal has existentially learned that he could rely on nothing
but his own self-imposed subjection to the law. The vassal, curiously enough,
therefore learns through his own self-subjection to the law what it would mean
to be a lawgiver, and he comes to see that the edicts of the master are
only the injunctions of a contingently formed individual, not the voice of
reason itself. As gradually coming to see that his own recognition of the
master is as crucial to the normative authority of the master's edicts as those
edicts are themselves, he also begins subtly to undermine the normative status
of the relationship in which both have found themselves, even if he, as vassal,
remains powerless to extricate himself from it. In doing so, though, he also
thereby comes to see his fate as resting on interest and power, not on right,
and, when that happens, the normatively "binding" quality of the
relationship has dissolved, even if the relations of power have not. pp. 228-229
Although neither the master nor the vassal
can discern it, in effect the same thing has happened to them in the dialectic
of self-consciousness that happened in consciousness: what had seemed to play the decisive normative role in underwriting
judgments turned out not to be what the proponents of that point of view
had taken it to be, but to be something else entirely. Neither the master's nor the vassal's will alone was normative for the
judgments of either agent; normative authority turned out to rest in the will
of both, in being a social matter of each serving as master and vassal, or, in
Kantian terms, of simultaneously, first, each subjecting the other to the law
he himself authors; second, of each being himself subject to the law
authored by the other; and, third, of each subjecting himself to the law of
which he is also the author. The
"truth" of the matter, as Hegel points out, is an "I that is a
We, and a We that is an I," that is, Geist,
a matter of sociality, not of individual awareness, desire, nor even of
mere coordination of competing perspectives. p. 229
Hegel seems to be suggesting the general
problem of coming to grips with the "Kantian paradox" only has a
historical solution, namely, that the move from a lawless will to a
certain kind of autonomy is to be taken as a historical, social achievement,
not as the realization of a metaphysical power that was all along operative in
us (as Hegel apparently thought Kant's doctrine of transcendental freedom
amounted to). The dawn of truly philosophical history thus begins with the
period when the
claims of reason were first addressed philosophically themselves,
when, that is, ways of life first began to reflectively come to grips with the
issue of what it meant to be a free agent as a rational agent. p. 230
The political and moral collapse of the
slave-owning societies of antiquity left the people of the ancient world
in the position of having to affirm their being laws unto themselves without
having to rely on slaves to affirm it for them, since it had become clear that
the slaves could not play that role. Both stoicism and skepticism (both as
philosophies and as ways of life) arose out of what seemed to be required by
that failure: one could only really
be a law unto oneself if, first, one engaged in practices of distancing oneself
from "life" and only taking as true what one could vouch for in one's
own free thought (as "stoicism"),
or, second (carrying that line of thought further), by taking a fully negative stance to all those putative claims to truth
(as skepticism) and thereby
preserving even more fully one's sense of being a law to oneself. Stoicism
attempts to make oneself a self-legislating "master" by creating a
practice of remaining free in thought even if not in body, whereas
skepticism is the attempt to secure the freedom of thought by turning it on
itself through a practice of doubting all claims. pp. 230-231
Neither stoicism nor skepticism, however, was
capable of sustaining itself - skepticism (as the truth of stoicism, as that to
which one is driven when one attempts to cash out the Stoic attempts at a free
life) ends up dissolving itself, since it ultimately has to submit its own
freedom to doubt to the same kind of skeptical questioning to which it submits
everything else, and, in doing so, exposes itself to itself as being only the
result of the contingent thoughts of a particular individual. p. 231
That
despair over ever getting it right suffused the philosophies of the ancient
world as the old gods and ways of life began dying out.
p. 231
The long-ruling medieval period of European
history, interpreted by Hegel as a reign
of universal servitude expressing itself as devotion to something
"higher," turned out to have as its "truth" (as what it
turned out to have required itself to formulate, given what it was trying to
accomplish) a view of a completely "objective" (God's eye) point
of view, which gradually came to be identified with reason itself as the
moderns came to believe that they could, in fact, comprehend the ways of
God. p. 231
In the long chapter of the Phenomenology
titled "Reason,"
Hegel gave a sweeping (and idiosyncratic) account of the early modern European attempt to fashion a science of
society, to translate the demand that one should be a law unto oneself into a
workable way of life. As a way of life, the attempt to become a law unto
oneself thus took increasingly individualistic forms; but as neither the Faustian pursuit of knowledge in the
service of satisfaction of desire, nor as the appeal to the "laws of the heart" (as laws to which
individuals appealed to justify their stance to social projects), nor as a
neo-stoic conception of virtue that identified true self-interest with the
greatest altruism, could such attempts at being
a law unto oneself sustain themselves. pp. 231-232
It,
too, unraveled under the pressure of practice and reflection upon its claims to
authority. In other words,
trying to hold onto the "authentic" self as the fixed point in our
otherwise contingent dealings with each other turned out not to be possible,
and it only served to show that there
simply was nothing fixed in the self that could play such a normative role.
The truth of the matter behind the
giving and asking for reasons, therefore, was an ongoing series of social
negotiations against a background of taken-forgranted
meanings, with everything in the negotiations being up for grabs. p. 232
The
dissolution of the notion of there being a "fixed," authentic self
behind the appearances of our actions was only resolved, so at least it at first seemed, by Kant's
conception of the agent as giving the law to himself in the form of maxims. That is, in the ongoing, contingent set of
social negotiations that seemed to be the "truth" of the modern
world, the only real truth to be found lay in agents
not looking to their identities to
fix their maxims, but instead looking to see which of those maxims could
be mutually (and ultimately, universally) legislated.
p. 232
KANTIAN PARADOX: Kant's own idea, though,
seemed to founder on what we have called the "Kantian paradox": it
both required there to be reasons preceding an individual's choice of reasons
in order for the choice to be reasonable; and it seemed to require that those
preceding reasons be themselves chosen. The Kantian solution, required by
the failures of what had come before it, thus threatened to dissolve on its own
part precisely because its appeal to "reason alone" seemed to rule
itself out because of the "paradox." The key issue concerning which
norms we elect and which we are simply called upon to "keep faith
with" thus seemed to be at risk in the Kantian (and therefore the modern)
solution itself. Retreating to a mere formalistic
interpretation of Kantian morality did not salvage the Kantian enterprise,
since the principle of non-contradiction rules nothing substantive out; nor did interpreting Kant's categorical
imperative as being only a procedural "test" of maxims taken from
elsewhere not beg the questions of the rationality of the origins of those
maxims. In that context, the modern crisis of reason and Jacobi's charges
of impending "nihilism" seemed all the more crucial to consider. p. 233
The
way out of the Kantian paradox, so Hegel thought, required us to comprehend how
we must at each point be both "master" and "slave" in
relation to each other, and how some form of self-legislation could be
compatible with such a conception. Answering that question in turn required a history of "social space," that is, an account of how the
history of the demands we have put on each other required us to develop a
determinate type of modern "social space," such that the modern, Kantian interpretation of the claims of
reason on us would come to be seen not as merely contingent, and perhaps
self-defeating, features of European history, but as something itself actually
required by the history of that "social space," or Geist.
p. 233
In that light, Hegel took Greek tragedy
– in particular, SophocleÕs Antigone
- to be especially revelatory of what it might mean for a way of life to be
based not on fully "giving the law to oneself" but on "keeping faith" with basic ethical laws. p. 234
Antigone is the true heroine of the play because she
alone truly understands the conflict (unlike Creon,
who for the greater part of the play seems to see no conflict at all, just
insubordination on Antigone's part), and she thus
understands that, although she must keep faith with the unconditional demand to
give her brother the proper burial rites, she is also guilty of violating the
unconditional demands of the civil law; and, even at the end of the play, she
knows she is guilty while at the same time holding fast to her view that she
did the right thing. 15 p.
234
15 SOCIAL ROLE
MUST BE UNDERSTOOD IN TERMS OF NORMATIVITY,
NOT THE OTHER WAY AROUND: In speaking of "keeping faith" with the
laws, I am modifying somewhat the way I spoke of the "immediate"
identity of Greek agents and their "social roles" in Pinkard, Hegel's Phenomenology. The language of "social
roles," as I have since found, obscures rather than reveals the crucial
notions of giving oneself the law and keeping faith with the law, also making it sound as if, for Hegel, the
Greek agent had never had to reflect on what she was required to do. p. 234 footnote
For the Greek spectator, however, who can
understand that she in fact suffers from conflicting demands, Antigone still appears as an almost unintelligible figure:
she is a woman (and the diminished role of women in Greek society is only too
obvious), and she also seems to be making her own choice
to be determinative of which law is to be obeyed, and thus in effect to be putting herself in
the contested role of the ultimate "tester" of valid law. The chorus
tells her that she has erred, saying, "Your self-sufficiency has brought
you down" (or, alternatively, and more literally, "your
self-recognized anger destroyed you"); Antigone's
anger is that of someone who recognizes only herself as an authority on the
issue at hand.16 Antigone thus displays in herself
how the normative demands of individuality acting according to personal
conscience are, as it were, struggling to emerge out of a situation where
there is no conception of conscience on which to base those actions; Antigone's plight is that of somebody experiencing an
immediate identification with her social role (as sister, as keeping
faith with the divine law), while at the
same time coming to experience that kind of immediate identification as
both impossible (and thus having already had
that identification wither within her own experience of herself) and inescapable,
as something simply required
of her. We moderns can see her conscience
at work; she can only experience the conflict and guilt.
p. 235
The self-destruction of the ethical harmony
of the ancient Greeks, and both the necessity for and the impossibility of the
emergence of individuality within that way of life, prepared the ground for the
Roman Empire to understand its own fragmented, "prosaic" way of life
as the Successor to the Greeks. p.
235
The French Revolution brought this to a close and completed, at least in principle, that line of development. Faced with the collapse of all other forms of authority, the "people," now describing themselves and not the monarch as the "nation of France," declared themselves "as the people" to be the "law" and to be engaged therefore in attaining an unconditional freedom normatively unconstrained by the past or the contingent features of human nature, but instead to be constrained only by what was necessarily involved in that freedom's being sought for its own sake, keeping faith with nothing outside of its own dictates – in short, claiming to be "absolute" freedom. However, without anything more definite to determine what counted as such self-determination, any government of the "nation" could only be a faction, a particular group with its own agenda, renaming its own interests as those of "the people" and characterizing those other factions opposed to it as a danger to the nation. The truth of "absolute freedom" was the Terror: giving the law to oneself freed from any constraint by a kind of rationality preceding such legislation, found its "truth" in the constant movement of the guillotine's blade.
pp. 236-237
To see it only in those terms, however, was
one-sided and therefore misleading. The
real truth of the French Revolution, so Hegel argued, were the Kantian and Fichtean revolutions in philosophy, for only they brought
out what was really normatively in play in the demand for "absolute
freedom" - not the Terror, but the Kantian kingdom of ends was the
"truth" of the demands of the Revolution. The Terror was, as it
were, the false conclusion that would be necessarily drawn from such a demand
without the mediating effects of social
institutions that themselves embodied and realized the kingdom of ends
(which Hegel, ever a child of his own times and upbringing, thought was some
form of Protestant Christianity, the religion of both himself and Kant). p. 237
The
Kantian and Fichtean
revolutions were themselves, however, also part of a larger way of life,
the very modern "moral worldview," as Hegel called it. While the
Terror emerged in France because of the way its institutional past as an
absolute, centralized monarchy made the claim of "the people" seem
like the rational embodiment of the demand of absolute freedom, in
fragmented Germany, the "moral worldview" at first emerged out of
developments in religion, not politics. For the "moral worldview," as
with the French Revolution, the primary object of concern was freedom, but
this was not taken in institutional terms (as a call to establish a government
of "absolute freedom") but instead as a call on oneself as an
individual, independently of all social conditions, to realize one's radical
freedom in both giving oneself the law and holding oneself to it. If the threat to freedom for the proponents
of the Revolution was governmental or aristocratic despotism,
the threat to freedom for the "moral worldview" was nature
(and especially one's own "human" nature of desires and
inclinations). To be free was to
be able to give oneself the law independently of any constraint by nature
(or social custom, although this was less important for the "moral
worldview"), and this could be actualized for an individual only by
holding fast to his self-legislated (although universal) duties. What
ultimately mattered for the "moral worldview" were that one exercise
a particular kind of power (such as transcendental freedom) that is independent
of nature, that one formulate one's maxims so as to meet the demands of universalizability, and that one act on the right motive
(do duty for duty's sake). This is a problem for individuals, not for
governments; no institution can make one transcendentally free, nor can it
prevent it; nor can an institution determine one's motive, for only the
individual himself can do that. pp.
237-238
The basic problem for the "moral
worldview" had to do with reconciling its claim to (individual,
moral) freedom with the competing claims made on an individual by his own
sensuous nature. In particular, it has to ask what interest the embodied
individual might have in being moral. On Kant's own terms, of course,
there could be no antecedent interest in being
moral, but even Kant himself
recognized that, whereas we could always demand of everyone that they do their
duty, we could not rationally expect everyone to be moral drudges, to live
lives of unremitting pain or stupefying dullness if morality required it.17 We are thus also under the duty to promote
the "highest good," the union of virtue and happiness, so that our desire for our own happiness
will not be at such odds with our clearly recognized moral duty. To that
end, Kant (and so many post-Kantians after him) attached great interest to
producing various "postulates"
of practical philosophy as necessary conditions of attaining the highest good
as the union of virtue and happiness (one example being Kant's arguing for
the practical necessity to postulate immortality and the promise of eternal
reward for our virtue). 18 p.
238
One
must strive to complete morality (bring about the highest good), and one must
also act without any interest
in its being actualized (since one's happiness is impermissible as a
moral motive). p. 239
The "moral worldview," so Hegel
argues, thereby commits itself to constant dissembling, a pretense that the
only thing that matters is acting on the motive of duty for duty's sake,
while at the same time claiming that, without attending to one's happiness, one
is engaged in a practically hopeless enterprise. p. 239
Behind
the "moral worldview" is a stress therefore on purity of
motive and purity of self,
of cleansing the agent of all contaminants to his ability to be a law unto
himself, and it is that commitment to purity that plays the determinative
normative role in the "moral worldview." Such a commitment
ultimately requires that the agent's uncontaminated commitment to duty be kept
pure, and, within the Christian European way of life, that commitment to purity
found its expression as the appeal to
personal conscience. Although Hegel held it was a
great achievement of modern life to have carved out a space for the claims of
conscience within itself, he also thought that the way that space had to be
carved out necessarily involved some false turns. At first, the appeal to conscience seemed
to be consistent only if it were taken in either of two ways: either the commitment to duty must be kept pure,
which rules out any action that might somehow soil that purity; or keeping one's purity intact required one to
act simply out of the depths of one's conviction, committed to the belief
that, whatever the outcome, the act was pure and therefore good if it was done
out of genuine, deep conviction. (Fichte held a version of this latter view, as
did]. F. Fries, who, of course, otherwise despised Fichte; in making his
criticisms, Hegel probably had Fries in mind, whom he detested as much as Fries
detested him.) The "pure" individual appealing only to what his
own conscience permits him is a "beautiful soul" (a term much in
vogue in Hegel's day and explicitly invoked in the moral context by Fries). For the "beautiful soul," one
avoids the "Kantian paradox" only by holding fast to one's
conscience, more or less "expressing" individually the moral law
that one personally "is." Hegel,
of course, could barely conceal his contempt for this line
of post- Kantian individualist self-absorption, but he also saw it as one of the ways in
which the "Kantian paradox" was working itself out as it tried to
realize the ideal of the morally pure will. '9 pp. 239-240
In their pursuit of purity in the face of the
fragmented, modern world, such beautiful souls fragment themselves into those who act out of conviction,
knowing that they cannot know all the possible morally salient features of a
situation but remain convinced that the purity of their conviction carries
over into their acts; and those who
cannot tolerate being contaminated by any compromises with the real world and
thus refuse to play along, preserving their inner purity by inaction and
condemning all those who act as complicit with the evil of the world. p. 240
In the eyes of the other, the judgmental purist, who refuses to soil
his hands with action that might compromise what his "pure"
conscience requires, is a hypocrite,
pretending to be good but actually concerned only with himself; in the eyes of
the judgmental purist, the agent who acts according to what the purity of his
conscience tells him is also a hypocrite, for the same reason. p. 240
In fact, each form of the beautiful soul
expresses something Kant already
anticipated: the moral ideal cannot mean that the demands of
duty are supposed to be the
normal case in everyday life, as if every waking moment in daily life should be
taken up with the thought of duty for duty's sake. Instead, it must mean that we are to strive to bring
about a world in which we quasi-naturally do
the right thing without having to constantly factor in our duty.20 p. 241
20 Seeing Kant in this way rejects the overly "rigorist"
interpretation of his views that only acts done from
duty have any moral worth - an interpretation that leads to Schiller's famous
jibe to the effect that we should set things up so that I dislike my friends so
that my good acts toward them will therefore shine all the brighter. Two recent
works go a long way toward dispelling such a view, substituting instead a view
that Kant was a "value" theorist, for whom "respect for
persons" is the ultimate value to be realized, and that all other duties
and moral considerations are to follow from that. See Allen Wood, Kant's
Ethical Theory (Cambridge University Press, 1999); and Nancy Sherman, Making
a Virtue of Necessity)': Kant and Aristotle on Virtue (Cambridge University
Press, 1997). The difficulties (both philosophical and textual) of making Kant
into such a "value theorist" are brought out by Robert Pippin,
"Kant's Theory of Value: On Allen Wood's Kant's Ethical Thought,"
Inquiry, 43 (summer, 2000); and "Rigorism and 'the New Kant',"
forthcoming in Proceedings of the IXth
International Kant Congress. p.
241 footnote
The solution to this, so Hegel argues, arises
out of the same practice that produces the appeal to conscience in the
first place, namely, Christian culture. In particular, it is the practice of
forgiveness, the Christian recognition that we are all "sinners" in
the eyes of God, transmuted
into a secular practice of forgiveness and
reconciliation that brings out
what is really normatively in play in the appeal to conscience: an appeal not
to "beautiful souls," but to the recognition that, in Hegel's terms, our sociality fundamentally commits us to
being the "masters" and "slaves" to each other - we are
authors of the law to ourselves only as others co-author the law for US.22
The "ethical world" - the "I that is
We, and the We that is I" - exists only in terms of each holding Ourselves
to the law by holding others to the law, while at the same time they hold us to
the law and hold themselves to the law; In all such cases, claims made on
oneself by another agent (or, in more Hegelian terms, by "the other")
radically
alter one's self-relation. The freedom sought by "beautiful souls" is thus to be
found not in a striving for independence (the problem with all attempts at being a "master" who is the
author of the law but never subject to a law authored by anybody else), but in a
recognition of our crucial mutual dependencies on each other.23 The "Kantian paradox" is not overcome,
only sublated, aufgehoben, into a historical and social
conception of agency, where the appeal to reason turns out to
involve, first, our participating in a historical, social practice of giving
and asking for reasons, not in an appeal to something outside of us that sorts
the world out for us prior to our deliberations, nor to any purely
methodological procedure of testing for universalizability; and, second, our understanding of freedom
as itself involving a certain type of self-relation that includes relations to
others as being in a common sphere, not the exercise of some transcendental,
causal power. pp.
241-242
23 This notion of "structured dependencies" is most explicitly worked out
by (and in fact the term comes from) Frederick Neuhouser,
Foundations of Hegel's Social Theory: Actualizing Freedom (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000).
p. 242
footnote
The concluding chapter on the history of Geist in the Phenomenology thus culminated not so much in a fixed conclusion, as in the sketch of a program
for Hegel's thought, arguing in effect that the modern world necessarily
had to make space for individuals and their inviolable consciences while at the
same time not becoming so individualistic that it failed to acknowledge the deep sociality of human agency.
(That is, "individualism" in Hegel became a "right of subjectivity," a normative demand
on how people should be regarded, not
a metaphysically prior fact about them that somehow was supposed to generate
such a demand.) This conclusion, though, comes about by relying on a
background understanding of a Christian "way of life," which serves
as a basis for articulating the commitments which such "beautiful
souls" actually have undertaken (or what in Hegelian terms is their
"truth"), and which is not itself to be found exclusively in those
commitments but must be generated out of them as what is really normatively in play in the kind of giving and asking for
reasons in modern social practice. Hegel's invocation of a
"Christian" way of life in that regard was done quite purposely,
since it raised for him the obvious question: is Christianity itself a rational
way of life, or just the way "we" (early nineteenth-century
Europeans) habitually do things? pp.
242-243
Given the rest of the argument in the Phenomenology, it is clear that, for Hegel, the only acceptable answer would have to be dialectical and historical.
One would first have to show that religion is itself something to which we must
be committed; and, second, show that Christianity, itself taken as a historical
practice, is also necessary, not just an accident of history; and, third, show
that its necessity is itself rational in the sense that it has emerged as what
was really normatively in play in other religions.
p. 243
It is clear that Hegel thought religion, at
least in the sense of being a communal practice involving a collective reflection on our (humanity's)
highest interests - on what ultimately matters to us - shares its concerns
with art and philosophy. In
Hegel's reconstruction, religious practice emerges in its earliest forms as
"nature religion" in which the divine is interpreted as an
abstract natural "whole" that does not necessarily concern
itself with humanity in particular; such "nature religions" in turn
culminate in Egyptian religious practices, in which, having reached the end of
their development, they set the stage for their own overcoming in Greek
religion, in which the gods present us
with an imaginative, aesthetic presentation of what it would
be like to be free, to be completely "laws unto
ourselves." The
replacement of harmonious Greek ethical
life by Roman imperial life in turn motivated a new focus on subjective
interiority that had itself emerged in an unsustainable form in the Greek
experience of becoming "philosophical." That development found its truth in the idea that God appeared as man
(Jesus) and died. (Hegel liked to cite an old Lutheran hymn to the effect
that "God has died."24) p.
243
The resurrection, Hegel seemed to say, occurs
in each Christian worship service in which God is present as rational self-conscious Geist
itself (However, Hegel did not think, as some of his left-Hegelian
followers later did, that, in religion, we worship only ourselves; he thought
that we acknowledged the "divine principle" in ourselves.)
Christianity, as a religion of humanity in general and not of a particular
nation, and as a religion of interiority
and freedom, not of authoritarian obedience, was the ground in which modern
life took root and flourished and could become reconciled with itself
Religion, that is, had always been about
what it means to be human; and, so it has turned out, what it means to be
human is to be a free agent, and what matters to us now in modern life -
"infinitely," ultimately - is that we be free, that we are called to
lead our own lives. p. 244
However,
even modern reformed Protestantism is not capable of formulating that
truth about itself. It
could at best express it through its practices of devotion, its rites, and its
symbols. p. 244
What
was normatively in play in Christian religion, Hegel was saying, had
turned out to be theology, the
articulation in rational form of what was only expressed in Christianity's
rites and rituals; but what
was normatively in play in theology,
in its appeal to reason, had turned out to be philosophy as "absolute knowing." p. 244
The Kantian "critique of reason"
(spread out over three Critiques and many other works), which asserted
the sovereignty of reason and its refusal to recognize anything "not
in its own plan" had culminated, so Hegel argued, in the historical triumph of philosophy, as non-religious, non-aesthetic
reflection on what mattered most to us, which was the historicized use of
reason itself to liberate ourselves from the dependencies on
givens that had shackled us in the past. pp. 244-245